2310586
код для вставкиThe Right to Refuse Treatment: Paradox, Pendulum and the Quality of Care Thomas G . Gutheil, M.D. This clinical and theoretical overview of the right to refuse treatment will address some of the themes that have dominated this area of intetface between psychiatry and the law, and have, perhaps, obscured the real concern of the right to refuse treatment question; i.e., the issue of quality of care. Central themes include factors present in the medicolegal context and recent events, origin of the concept of the right to treatment, the separation of conjinement from treatment, and the changing models of vicarious decision making. This review also addressesjudicial conceptdizations of treatment, including the concept of quarantine,judicial risk-aversiveness,and judicialfantasies of drug action. Some possible directionsfor the future are also examined. INTRODUCTION In presenting an overview on the right to refuse treatment, this article will address some of the themes that have dominated this area of interface between psychiatry and law. Other articles in this volume will cover in detail the separate elements of this broad topic. An anecdote from my pediatrics internship may serve to highlight the central concerns. I frequently found on followup visits with Hispanic families whose children I was treating, that the baby had not been given its medication correctly or, had not been given it at all. Gradually it became clear that my act of prescribing, to which I brought all my nascent skills as diagnostician and pharmacologist, was not the final step in the process, as I imagined it to be, but only the first. After the prescription had been written and the family had listened Thomas G . Gutheil, M.D.,is the Co-Director, Program in Psychiatry and Law,Massachusetts Mental Health Center, Boston, Mass.Correspondence and reprint requests should be oddressed to: Thomas G. Gutheil, M.D., Massachusetts Mental Health Center, 74 Fenwood Road,Boston, MA 02115. The author acknowledges his indebtedness to Lcslie M. Levi for assistance in the preparation of this manuscript. Behavioral Sciences & the Law, Vol. 4, No. 3, pp. 265-277 (1986) CCC 0735-3936/86/030265-13$04.00 0 1986 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. 266 Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care politely to my instructions, the prescription and my instructions were brought before the grandfather of the family for discussion and decision-making. He would be the actual arbitrator of how the medicine should be taken, or even if it should be taken at all. This anecdote captures several elements central to understanding the concept of the right to refuse treatment. CENTRAL THEMES IN THE RIGHT TO REFUSE TREATMENT Paternalism In treating patients, physicians often have been accused of paternalism in their approach. In psychiatric inpatient settings, the physician often acted in what he or she perceived to be the patient’s best interests, regardless of the patient’s position on the matter. A patient seen as needing treatment was given that treatment based on the view that “doctor knows best.” A patient out of control, or whose refusal was clearly a part of the illness, received what amounted to an ad hoc determination by the clinician of incompetence to consent to or refuse treatment. After two or three days of involuntary medication, the patient was usually in touch with the situation, taking medication voluntarily, asking for increased privileges, and demanding to know when the family was going to visit. This medical decision-making view has slipped out of and back into vogue with the judiciary. In my initial anecdote, medical paternalism was supplanted by cultural paternalism, a condition perhaps more closely resembling real life. As Stimson (1974) has noted, the recipient of a prescription does not live in an informational vacuum, but receives an enormous amount of data about illness and treatment from many sources. Furthermore, although my patients were minors, even competent adult outpatients weigh the value of the prescription against internalized and external value systems, often of a paternalistic nature (Gutheil, 1982). Autonomy The clinical anecdote also touches on the theme of autonomy, a second essential principle in the right to refuse treatment. Here, the family maintained their autonomy from medical decision-making, but surrendered it to the equivalent of a tribal elder. The question of maintaining autonomy grows even more complex for inpatients mandated to be under a doctor’s care. How much autonomy should be granted to this population and to what degree? Is the essence of preserving autonomy fully realized by the use of informed consent? Under what circumstances should preservation of autonomy-ethically , as well as clinically desirable-be sacrificed for some higher good, such as safety or rapid release BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES & THE LAW Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care 267 from confinement? Is the patient ceding his or her autonomy involuntarily to the disease? That is, is the patient or the illness “talking?’ Closely related to the last point is the idea of freedom. Is freedom of choice preferable to a freedom from illness? That is, since involuntary hospitalization might be construed as a temporary decrease in liberty in exchange for a more definitive gain in liberty (i.e., from the illness and its consequent risks and suffering), might involuntary treatment offer the same tradeoff: a short-range incursion on liberty in exchange for a more fundamental liberation? Competence The concept of competence to consent to treatment, one of the elements of informed consent, is less obvious in the anecdote, yet it is present at two levels. First, the children to whom the medication was given were not competent on the basis of age to decide about their treatment. Second, their parents, as presumably competent adults, could have made valid decisions about the medications. They elected, however, to cede their decision-making capacity to the elder in the family. In analogous ways, many patients, in and out of hospitals, cede their decision-making capacity to their physician, saying, in effect: “I don’t know what’s the best choice here; you go ahead and do what you think is best and I’ll trust your judgment.” I have suggested that an informal competence assessment (with a finding of incompetence to make treatment decisions) was taking place at those points where patients’ refusals of needed treatment were overridden by clinicians. Most discussions of autonomy presume autonomous choices by competent individuals. While inpatients vary in actual competence, a conceptually interesting question alluded to earlier is whether involuntary commitment as a principle, legal statutes aside, represents a de fact0 determination of incompetence to make treatment choices generally, or whether medical treatment decisions lie in a separate realm of decision-making, requiring separate procedures or sanctions. This question is discussed in detail later. The Physician’s View Finally, the anecdote hints at the physician’s bewilderment at the fact that the patient is refusing orjejecting his or her recommendations made with the best interests of the patient at heart. It is not simply that the patient appears to be opposing the, physician, but to be opposing the patient’s own best interests. In the anecdote this posture has a cultural basis. In most clinical settings the illness and its effects on decision-making are held to account for the self-defeating acts. But, the core of the experience for the clinician in either case is the feeling of being asked to care for a patient whom he or she cannot treat in the best way possible. VOL. 4 NO. 3 1986 268 Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care HISTORICAL DEVELOPMENT OF THE RIGHT TO REFUSE TREATMENT In 1974 an important summary article appeared in the Harvard Law Review discussing developments in the issue of civil commitment (3). The articlecontains this observation: Inherent in an adjudication that an individual should be committed . . . is the decision that he can be forced to accept treatments . . .; it would be incongruous if an individual . . . could frustrate the very justification for the state’s action by refusing such treatment. The reasoning underlying this point can readily be grasped to commit someone involuntarily to a mental institution without treatment for the illness that is the underlying basis for such confinement would be tantamount to warehousing him or her, that is, to confining without hope of reversing the process that resulted in the confinement. Moreover, since patients, unlike criminals, could be confined by statute in many jurisdictions without actually having “done anything,” that is, by posing only the threat of imminent harm on the basis of mental illness, their rights would be thus doubly violated if one separates their confinement from treatment. In 1985, a Wisconsin court held that committed patients did not have a right to refuse treatment. In his opinion, the judge observed: “Non-consensualtreatment is what involuntary commitment is all about.” The naive student might conclude, on examining the conceptual positions here juxtaposed, that the issue of the right to refuse treatment had not changed significantly in these 11 years. These authorities seemed to agree that involuntary patients must be treated, even involuntarily, as a condition of their confinement, and that it would be paradoxical if the patient’s presumably illness-based refusal of hospitalization and treatment (thus forcing involuntary hospitalization) permitted them to refuse treatment, the need for which, in part, justified their hospitalization. Fundamental Issue: Quality of Care I have suggested (Appelbaum & Gutheil, 1981) that the quality of care that a patient receives is latent in discussions of the right to refuse treatment. Even when the issue is argued on constitutional grounds, an historical perception of the deficient levels of staffing and care available in most state hospitals influences the attitudes of advocates and others. Militating for a right to refuse treatment appears to offer one narrow pathway toward improvement of conditions in hospitals. Ironically, as Gill (1982) has suggested, it appears that the actual effect may be the opposite. By delaying treatment and placing patients and staff in an 1. Stensvad v. Reivitz (D.C.Wisc 84-C-383-5, Jan 10, 1985). BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES & THE LAW Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care 269 adversarial relationship, marginal state hospital conditions may actually be made worse by the establishment of a formal right to refuse treatment. Regrettably there is a considerable dearth of long-term information on the actual sequelae of recently established rights to refuse treatment. Some multicenter studies in progress should shed further light on this point. Right to Treatment This concept, coined by Birnbaum (1960) began to become a factor in judicial thinking about psychiatric inpatients through a series of As suggested earlier, patients confined to a state hospital should receive treatment beyond custodial care to justify that confinement. Here, also, the issue of quality of care first received explicit judicial definition, through guidelines on the minimum standards of treatment. The Commitment/Treatment Schism Another evolving concept is what might be termed the commitment/treatment schism or separation. Once considered inseparable, these two elements began receiving separate and distinct judicial consideration, Le., the one did not necessarily flow from the other. Subsumed in this shift was an alteration of the critical question from one of dangerousness to one of competence. When commitment served as a response to dangerousness, treatment could be seen as another factor decreasing the danger, as well as justifying the confinement itself. If the question is reformulated in terms of the competence of the patient to participate in the treatment decisionmaking, dangerousness aside, then the situation is altered in a manner that might seem puzzling at first. Commitment only occurs when the patient refuses the intervention of hospitalization. Although “danger from mental illness” is the reason given, one can assume that this refusal is being treated as though it were an incompetent decision, i.e., illness based. Why, one could ask, does this not apply to an apparently similar illness-based refusal of another intervention, i.e., medication? One possible answer lies in the compartmentalization of much judicial reasoning, a point that will be addressed in more detail later. Thus, short-term treatment interventions may, like commitment, be justified in emergencies. For example, patients may receive medications for dangerousness criteria similar to those of commitment, i.e., risk of imminent harm. Longer term interventions such as treatment regimens with daily divided doses, appear to represent something different to the judiciary, which here invoke the informed consent model, based on competence. Thus, the commitmentheatment schism and concomitant shift from danger2. Wyatt v. Stickney 325 F. Supp. 781 (MD Ala 1971). 3. O’Connor v. Donaldson 422 U.S.563; 95 S.Ct.2486 (1975). VOL. 4 NO.3 1986 270 Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care ousness to competence criteria synergize to produce the dilemmas addressed in this issue. Patients as Minorities Part of the socioculturalbackground for the right to refuse treatment legislation flows from the growth in interest in minority rights during the late ’60’s and early ’70’s. Hospitalized mental patients were seen by legal advocates and others as oppressed minorities in need of advocacy or other legal interventions. Hence, a number of patients’ rights, including the right to refuse treatment, became of interest. Issues for Lawyers The same era saw the development of what has been called the “mental health bar” (Gutheil & Appelbaum, 1982), that is, the development among groups of attorneys of specialized interest in and familiarity with mental health issues, procedures, and problems. Psychiatrists began to appear on law school faculties to meet the educational needs resulting from this growth of interest. The development of “no-fault trends” in various areas of civil practice (e.g., auto insurance) may also have played an indirect role in diverting attorneys into other fields of practice. This is likely to have had a greater influence on private sector psychiatry, rather than on the state hospital system, for obvious economic reasons, Changing Models of Vicarious Decision-Making Historically, decision-making on behalf of mental patients was informal, to say the least. Clinicians faced with a patient manifestly too sick to make his or her own decisions could turn to family members, court-appointed guardians, or judges. Often, as noted earlier, the physician acted as the ad hoc guardian of the patient, making the decision in the best interests of the patient. This “best interests” standard, popular for many years, has been yielding to a new standard of “Substituted judgment.” Simply put, this judgment represents the attempt by the vicarious decision-maker to divine what the incompetentperson would do if they were competent. This model attempts to individualize vicarious decision-making and to free the process from possible bias stemming from ambiguity about whose “best interests,” the person’s or the decider’s, are being considered. Ironically, a fundamentally irresolvable paradox is created when this model is applied to the right to refuse treatment with antipsychotics, a paradox which is ignored in most legal discussions of the matter. When substituted judgment is required because the patient has been rendered incompetent by mental illness, the decision to be faced is whether or not to consent to treatment with antipsychotics. These drugs will then ostensibly restore the patient to his pre-illness BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES & THE LAW Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care 27 1 competence. But before he was ill and incompetent, he had no need for the drugs. Thus, when you ask what the incompetent patient would want if he were competent (substituted judgment), you are essentially asking, “If this patient were well, what medication would he choose for his illness?” This paradox is heightened by the reality that while many individuals prepare for future death in various ways, almost no one prepares for future incompetence. As a result, the substituted judgment model of vicarious decision-making may be as much a guessing game in practice as the “best interests” model seemed to be. Clinical Context During the same period the state hospital system nationwide was swept by storms of varying descriptions. Funding cuts and state hospital closings vied with messianic attempts at deinstitutionalizationfor which would exert the greater disruptive effect on the delivery of mental health care. Depending on the quality of care available, involuntary treatment in this system often resulted in mismedication, overmedication, medication for sedation only, and similar abuses. These pharmacologic failures often joined with, or were caused by, underfunding and understaffing, such that one doctor covered 300 patients, or absent a doctor, aides or other medically untrained persons made medication decisions. In slightly better settings, patients who were promptly (if involuntarily) treated returned to self control and competence and were discharged. Often, however, aftercare was inadequate such that monitoring of medication compliance or other elements of continuing care were deficient. This resulted in rapid return to the hospital and the development of what has been called the “revolving door syndrome.” Judicial Conceptualizations of Treatment We must touch briefly upon some of the perceptions of psychopharmacologic treatment prevalent among the judiciary during this period. These perceptions are gleaned from case law, legal articles, and empirical research. Concept of Quarantine The first issue is the concept of quarantine for mental, not infectious, diseases. This was given explicit expression in Rogers v. By this reasoning, the mentally ill and dangerous individual was to be quarantined from his or her fellow citizens to prevent, presumably, the contagion of his or her danger. Noteworthy in Federal District Court Judge Joseph Tauro’s opinion is the secondary role of actual treatment: “We know that the committed mental patient has been quarantined from house, family and society . . . The involuntarypatient 4. Rogers v. Okin 478 F. Supp. 1342 (D. Mass. 1979). VOL. 4 NO. 3 1986 272 Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care was committed primarily to quarantine that patient from the outside world, hopefully to be treated and cured . . .” The issue here of quarantine as the primary object of hospitalization resonates with a complaint frequently expressed by clinicians in two scenarios: (a) when an advocate, having achieved by means of a hearing the release of a patient, loses interest in the patient’s welfare once the hearing is over and the civil rights question is resolved, or b) when a committed patient, too ill or dangerous to be released, has won the right to refuse treatment and remains stuck in therapeutic limbo, “rotting with his rights on,” as elsewhere expressed (Appelbaum & Gutheil, 1979). In each case the naive clinician asks the attorney, “Okay, you’ve won the case, now what do we do with the patient?“, to which the attorney replies, “How should I know? I’m not a doctor (social worker, placement aide, community agency, etc.).” Like such advocates, some judges also lose interest in the eventual fate of the patient after the hearing; the clinician, however, remains necessarily involved. Judicial Risk-Aversiveness Although this point is not often stressed, judges tend to be risk-aversive in their general approach to decision-making. That is, since no one demands legal redress for an advantage that they have accrued, the court’s experience is more oriented towards determining degrees of risk, harm, cost, or losses than determining benefits. Courts do not usually perform the prospective risk-benefit balancing assessments that are the essence of clinical decision-making. A remarkable example of this point occurred in the Roe’ case, ancestor to the Rogers case. The Massachusetts Supreme JudiciaI Court quoted heavily from a famous antimedication polemic (Plotkin, 1977), but quoted only one line from a legitimate pharmacologic source. The shocking degree of bias revealed by the court is rendered perhaps slightly comprehensible if we understand that the court isn’t really interested in the good that drugs do, but only in the harms, since issues of compensation and infringement of rights are perceived as deriving from risks, not benefits. Empirical confirmation of this point is found in an as yet unpublished survey comparing judges’ and psychiatrists’ estimations of risks of tardive dyskinesia when prescribing antipsychotics to prevent psychosis. This study found the two groups agreeing on the likelihood of occurrence of this effect. For judges this risk was unacceptably high; for doctors, acceptably low (Bursztajn et al., unpublished). Judicial Fantasies of Drug Action An extensive survey of civil and criminal court opinions on the mechanisms of action of antipsychotic drugs revealed that criminal courts appear to achieve clear and reasonable perceptions of how drugs work, based on expert testimony. However, civil courts frequently appear to feel a freedom to characterize drugs in idiosyncratic, often polemic ways (Gutheil & Appelbaum, 1983). More sigBEHAVIORAL SCIENCES & THE LAW Gutheil:Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care 273 nificantly, the right hand, so to say, not only does not know what the left hand is doing, but fails to acknowledge its existence. Less metaphorically, the civil and criminal cases usually do not cite each other, so that the separation of these two streams of information is preserved. A range of judicial fantasies concerning psychiatric treatment exists. The most common one is the view of drugs as “mind-altering.” Though strictly true in the mind-restoring sense, this term is used pejoratively, in the sense of mind control. In a famous judicial excess, Judge Tauro attempted to make a First Amendment, freedom-of-speech issue out of this perceived mechanism, seeming to defend a patient’s freedom of psychotic speech and thought, as though the clinician were attempting to suppress dissenting ideas, rather than to treat a d i ~ e a s e Other .~ fantasies include views of antipsychotics as “undermining the foundations of the personality,” as being similar to ECT and psychosurgery, and as creating an artificial competence (Gutheil & Appelbaum, 1983). Legal Quanta vs. Clinical Continua One communicative difficulty at the clinical-legal interface stems from judicial compartmentalization, i. e., perceptions of treatment interventions as discrete quanta, or separate events, rather than as elements of a continuous flow of treatment (Gutheil & Mills, 1982). In right to refuse treatment cases, this has been termed “one punch, one shot” reasoning. Thus, the inpatient punches a staff member, demonstrating acute danger and justifying an emergency intervention, inappropriately limited by the court to one injection (“shot”) of medication, rather than to the safer, wiser, and more appropriate response, i.e., initiation of a course of treatment aimed at successfully attaining those blood levels of drug needed to treat the underlying disease. When the shot wears off, the patient, whose illness has not been significantly treated, may repeat the process indefinitely, a circumstance exposing the patient to all the risks and none of the benefits of treatment. Advocates argue that medication after the initial shot has not been justified, because the patient is not dangerous enough immediately afterward to merit more medication. Again, only a compartmentalized view makes these curious conceptualizations comprehensible. Some Realities of Due Process For advocates, due process represents the sovereign remedy for disagreements within a system, often to the point that one suspects due process as representing an end in itself for the more extreme members of this group. For the busy clinician the value of the often cumbersome court-related procedures (the affidavits, the certificates, the hearings, and the actual experiences on the witness stand) often appear to be unjustified drains on the most precious treatment resource, that being time carefully spent with a patient by a competent clinician. 5. In the matter of guardianship of Richard Roe 111 421 N.E. 2d 40 (Mass. 1981). VOL. 4 NO.3 1986 214 Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care From a purely legal standpoint, due process is intended to be slow, cumbersome, and expensive, for the simple reason that protection of civil rights often requires such prophylactic ponderousness, For the clinician attempting to treat a nonemergent, but intervention-requiring patient, however, this line of reasoning is often unconvincing, especially for inpatients, since the clinician must still house and care for the patient, who continues to consume bed space and nursing resources, even if treatment is delayed or precluded. In actual practice the implementation of the right to refuse treatment is highly variable, as is the degree of due process deemed necessary to achieve the desired conflict resolution (Gutheil, 1985). At one extreme, a full adversarial evidentiary hearing before a judge is required.6 In other settings various extrajudicial or quasijudicial procedures may be sufficient (Hoge et al., unpublished). Empirical results are preliminary and varied, but some findings are of interest. First, in the most restrictive of settings, the fewest cases are brought for actual review, and the overwhelming majority of those cases of patient reusal are overturned, i.e., the judge orders that the patient be treated. In more informal and less restrictive settings, more cases are reviewed and more refusals by patients are honored (Hoge et al., unpublished). These surprising, even paradoxical, findings strike directly at the question of the purpose of due process: if the purpose is to have a hearing, then the hearing is needed; if to protect the patient’s freedom to refuse, then informal methods may more realistically achieve this end. Unfortunately, the judiciary’s lack of interest in what happens to the patient after the hearing is only matched by its lack of interest in empirical realities such as these. A Core DBiculty: “Critogenesis” Medicine already has the term “iatrogenesis” to refer to a medical problem caused by the practice of medicine; the law has no such term, so that members of the Program in Psychiatry and the Law at the Massachusetts Mental Health Center have tried to fill this need devising the term, “critogenesis” (from the Greek word, “crites” meaning Athenian judge) to refer to harms or problems caused by legal procedures and processes themselves, regardless of how wisely applied (Bursztajn, 1986). A familiar example of a critogenic harm is the adversarializationof the doctor-patient relationship. This major threat to the alliance stems from the fact that, since the doctor wants the patient to be treated and the patient is saying that he or she does not want this, the two “parties” are in conflict. This primitive conceptualization ignores the ambivalences present in both doctor and patient about treatment. Areas that might be productively discussed, explored, or explained are ignored. The fact that the patient may both wish and not wish to be treated, as the doctor may both wish and not wish to 6. Rogers v. Commissioner of Mental Health S-2995, Mass (Nov. 29, 1983). BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES & THE LAW Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care 275 impose treatment is not addressed in such an adversarial setting. In the legal setting the issue is distorted through simplification: the two sides of the case (or, more accurately, the attorneys for both sides) oppose each other. Another layer of complexity results from the fact that courts often portray the doctor as inherently in conflict with the patients under his or her care. For example, if the doctor has several patients on the same ward and one of the doctor’s patients attacks another of the doctor’s patients, then in stopping patient A to protect patient B, the doctor is countering A’s actions for reasons that allegedly have to do with B’s interests, and not A’s. . . . the doctors who are attempting to treat as well as to maintain order . . . have interests in conflict with those of their patients who may wish to refuse medication.”6 This similarly primitive conceptualization also ignores the value spread among both patients and the surrounding milieu from such intervention, which is in everyone’s interests, not just patient B’s. Yet another point of possible friction between legal and medical models in this area flows from the patients themselves. When advocates advance what they perceive to be the patient’s interest, they often do not take into account other, sometimes predominant, interests or wishes in which the patients may be invested, yet which are not questions of rights or entitlements with which advocates are most comfortable. An example of this stems from the time when guardianships were required if a patient was thought to be incompetent in refusing, or for that matter accepting, medication. The patient, a long-term inmate at the hospital, rarely refused his medications, which he realized were to help him. During the furor around the right to refuse treatment, he had decided to exercise this right and refused his medication. Staff explained to him the details of the procedure whereby his case would be ruled upon by the court, which, if it agreed that he was incompetent, would appoint a guardian to decide on his behalf. At that the patient exclaimed, “To hell with that! I don’t want a guardian, I’d rather just take the medication.” In this example, the due process protections were viewed by the patient as more trouble than they were worth. Other similar patient views might include the wish not to appear in open court, not to get into struggles with the treatment staff, not to oppose their doctor’s wishes, and the like. For these patients, procedural mechanisms may be a liability, not an asset. THE OUTLOOK FOR THE FUTURE Speculation in medicolegal areas is always problematic since fad and trend can surprise the most experienced scholars. We can identify, however, some possible areas within which future developments may lie. VOL. 4 NO.3 1986 276 Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care CommitmentD’reatment “Fusion” As signaled by the Stensvad case at the outset,’ one possible trend is the recombination of commitment and treatment, whereby the patient’s refusal of hospitalization and of medications, both as required treatment interventions, are linked by being grouped as “nonconsensual treatment.” This would be clinically defensible and has now once again been made legally defensible. Procedural Changes and Accelerations A multiplicity of models are at least theoretically available for achieving the requisite level of due process to satisfy the judiciary in a given jurisdiction. We will probably see the growth of in-house review panels and other nonjudicial models, since recent Supreme Court rulings have stacked the deck in favor of deferring to medical judgment when that judgment has clearly been exercised.’ Peer review models should satisfy this requirement admirably, as well as responding far faster than courtroom proceedings with no less protection for the patient. Finally, due process may feed upon itself, as it were, when hospital attorneys are able to exert pressure to require even those full judicial hearings to be genuinely “speedy,” since the delay inherent in full proceedings always costs everyone, especially the patient. Legislative mandates requiring very short “latencies” for such hearings might represent one such similar approach. Precommitment Competency Assessment One of the most interesting developments in the area of the right to refuse treatment represents a variation on the fusion of commitment and treatment. This model requires a finding of incompetence to consent to or refuse treatment as a criterion of commitability. This model already exists in two forms. A famous Utah case held that the treating physician could ovemde the patient’s refusal of medication, since the Utah legislature had recently enacted a commitment statute requiring a judicial finding of incompetence before the patient could be committed.*Since the patient had already had this exercise of due process, the physician could make the treatment decision, serving in effect as the patient’s guardian. A similar conceptualization is the basis of the American Psychiatric Association’s Model Commitment Statute which proposes commitment only for those incompetent to make treatment decisions (Stromberg & Stone, 1984). The central advantage of this model is that it ensures a patient will not be committed to an institution that is not authorized to treat him or her, and thus prevents patients 7. Youngberg v. Romeo 50 U.S.L.W.4681 (June 15, 1982). 8. AE and RR v. Mitchell No. C78-466 (D-Utah, June 16, 1980). BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES & THE LAW Gutheil: Paradox, Pendulum, Quality of Care 271 from “rotting with their rights on.” It remains to be seen what impact this model will have on actual practice in varying jurisdictions. CONCLUSION More than many medicolegal issues, the right to refuse treatment captures the full impact of the ancient Chinese curse, which invokes: “May you live in interesting times.” This overview has attempted to review the “interesting time” of this thorny issue and to sketch in the scope and complexity, the paradoxes and pendulums, of this controversial attempt to ensure what is always the clinician’s aim: improvement of the quality of care. The other articles in this issue will sharpen our focus on the diverse elements (clinical, legal, and empirical) on this topic. REFERENCES Appelbaum, P. S., & Gutheil, T. G . (1979). Rotting with their rights on: Constitutional theory and clinical reality in drug refusal by psychiatric patients. Bulletin of rhe American Academy of Psychiatry and Law, 7,308-317. Appelbaum, P. S., & Gutheil, T. G. (1981). The right to refuse treatment: the real issue is the quality of care. Bullerin of the American Academy of Psychiatry and Law, 9.199-202. Birnbaum, M. (1960). The right to treatment. American Bar Association Journal, 46,499-505. Bursztajn, H. (1986) More law and less protection: “critogenesis,” “legal iaaogenesis,” and medical decision making. Journal of Geriatric Psychiarry 18,143-153. Bursztajn, H. et al. Empirical differences between psychiatrists’ and judges’ risk perceptions of tardive dyskinesia in prescribing anti-psychotic medications. (Unpublished manuscript). Developments in the law--civil commitment of the mentally ill. Harvard Law Review, 87(6),1190-1406, 1974. Gill, M. T. (1982). Side effects of a right to refuse treatment lawsuit: The Boston State Hospital experience. In A. E. Boudera, & 1. P. Swazey (Eds.), Refusing Treatment in Menral Health Instirurions, AM Arbor, Mich.: AUPHA Press. Gutheil, T. G. (1982). The psychology of psychopharmacology.Bulletin of the Meninger Clinic. 46,321-330. Gutheil, T. G., & Appelbaum, P. S . (1982). Clinical Handbook of Psychiatry and the Law. New York: McGrawHill. Gutheil, T. G . , & Appelbaum, P. S. (1983). Mind control, synthetic sanity, artificial competence, and genuine confusion: Legal relevant actions of antipsychotic drugs. Hofsrra Law Review, 22,77-120. Gutheil, T. G..& Mills, M. 1. (1982). Legal conceptualizations, legal fiction, and the manipulation of reality: Conflict between models of decision-making and psychiatry and law. Bulletin of the American Academy of Psychiatry and rhe Law, 10,17-27. Gutheil, T. G. (1985). Rogers v. Commissioner:The denouement of an important right-to-refuse treatment case. American Journal of Psychiarry. 142,213-216. Hoge, S . K., Gutheil, T. G . , & Kaplan, E. The right to refuse treatment under Rogers v. Commissioner:Preliminary empirical findings and comparisons. (unpublished manuscript). Plotkin, R. (1977). Limiting the therapeuticorgy: Mental Patients’ right to refuse treatment. Northeastern Universiry Lnw Review, 72,461-525. Stimson, G. V. (1974). Obeying doctor’s orders: a view from the other side. Sociaf Science and Medicine, 8,97-104. Stomberg, D.C., & Stone, A. A. (1984). A model state law on civil commitment of the mentally ill. Issues in Forensic Psychiatry (pp. 57-180). Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Press. VOL. 4 NO.3 1986
1/--страниц